谁能用英文介绍下柏拉图(Platon)的思想,字数不限! 谁能用英文介绍下柏拉图Platon的思想

\u8c01\u80fd\u7528\u82f1\u6587\u4ecb\u7ecd\u4e0b\u67cf\u62c9\u56fe(Platon)\u7684\u601d\u60f3\uff0c\u5b57\u6570\u4e0d\u9650\uff01

Platonic philosophy attempted to capture essence in a different way. Plato thought what we see in the physical world is a dim reflection of the true ideal thing. For example circular objects are crude approximations to the ideal perfect circle. Platonic analysis aims to understand the physical world in terms of the ideals that capture the real essence that is dimly reflected in physical existence.

Today the ideal world that captures the true circle is mathematics. Unlike Euclidean geometry, contemporary mathematics has no primitive objects with innate properties. In mathematics everything is structure. Mathematical captures the mathematical properties of the ideal circle as an abstract structure.

Removing essence from primitive objects in mathematics serves a valuable purpose. It forces all structure to be explicit. One avoids implicit assumptions about objects by way of assumed properties of those objects. For example it was long thought that logic required that parallel lines never meet. Eventually mathematicians realized that this was an assumption that is true in some geometries and not true in others. In particular it is not true on the surface of a sphere which is the geometry we inhabit.

Mathematics avoids making implicit assumptions by limiting itself to one primitive entity, the empty set, with no structure of its own. It is far more difficult to construct a geometry from the empty set than it is from the axioms of Euclid. But when mathematicians do it in the contemporary way they fully characterize the structures they are building. This helps them to see other ways in which a different geometry might be constructed. It also helps them to understand how seemingly disparate fields of mathematics may be structurally similar and able to borrow results from each other.

Essence free arguments are not the norm even in mathematics. Geometrical arguments are still phrased in terms of geometrical properties. Only they are done in such a way that it is clear how to convert them to arguments about sets. In normal discourse we take the merger of structure and essence as given. It is how we visualize the world and how we think. The problem is that the essence we attribute to external objects is from our own experience. It is not something that is part of the external objects. A soft touch, sharp slap, beautiful sunset or ugly wound, are things created in us when we have particular experiences.

We are not perceiving external reality as it truly is nor are we dimly perceiving some ideal platonic reality. We are creating the world in our conscious experience. There is a related external structure that exists as its own immediate experience. Our perception is causally connected to this structure. But the perception of for example color is for more a construction of our sensory and nervous system than it is an effect from light of a particular frequency

\u4f60\u53bb\u4e0b\u8f7d\u4e00\u672c\u82f1\u6587\u7248\u7684\u300a\u7406\u60f3\u56fd\u300b
\u7136\u540e\u7167\u6284\u5c31\u884c

柏拉图的思想
Plato often discusses the father-son relationship and the "question" of whether a father's interest in his sons has much to do with how well his sons turn out. A boy in ancient Athens was socially located by his family identity, and Plato often refers to his characters in terms of their paternal and fraternal relationships. Socrates was not a family man, and saw himself as the son of his mother, who was apparently a midwife. A divine fatalist, Socrates mocks men who spent exorbitant fees on tutors and trainers for their sons, and repeatedly ventures the idea that good character is a gift from the gods. Crito reminds Socrates that orphans are at the mercy of chance, but Socrates is unconcerned. In the Theaetetus, he is found recruiting as a disciple a young man whose inheritance has been squandered. Socrates twice compares the relationship of the older man and his boy lover to the father-son relationship (Lysis 213a, Republic 3.403b), and in the Phaedo, Socrates' disciples, towards whom he displays more concern than his biological sons, say they will feel "fatherless" when he is gone. Many dialogues, like these, suggest that man-boy love (which is "spiritual") is a wise man's substitute for father-son biology (which is "bodily").

In several dialogues, Socrates floats the idea that Knowledge is a matter of recollection, and not of learning, observation, or study. He maintains this view somewhat at his own expense, because in many dialogues, Socrates complains of his forgetfulness. Socrates is often found arguing that knowledge is not empirical, and that it comes from divine insight. He is quite consistent in believing in the immortality of the soul, and several dialogues end with long speeches imagining the afterlife. More than one dialogue contrasts knowledge and opinion, perception and reality, nature and custom, and body and soul. The only contrast to this is his Parmenides.

Several dialogues tackle questions about art: Socrates says that poetry is inspired by the muses, and is not rational. He speaks approvingly of this, and other forms of divine madness (drunkenness, eroticism, and dreaming) in the Phaedrus (265a–c), and yet in the Republic wants to outlaw Homer's great poetry, and laughter as well. In Ion, Socrates gives no hint of the disapproval of Homer that he expresses in the Republic. The dialogue Ion suggests that Homer's Iliad functioned in the ancient Greek world as the bible does today in the modern Christian world: as divinely inspired literature that can provide moral guidance, if only it can be properly interpreted.

On politics and art, religion and science, justice and medicine, virtue and vice, crime and punishment, pleasure and pain, rhetoric and rhapsody, human nature and sexuality, love and wisdom, Socrates and his company of disputants had something to say.

Main article: Platonic realism
"Platonism" is a term coined by scholars to refer to the intellectual consequences of denying, as Socrates often does, the reality of the material world. In several dialogues, most notably the Republic, Socrates inverts the common man's intuition about what is knowable and what is real. While most people take the objects of their senses to be real if anything is, Socrates is contemptuous of people who think that something has to be graspable in the hands to be real. In the Theaetetus, he says such people are "eu a-mousoi", an expression that means literally, "happily without the muses" (Theaetetus 156a). In other words, such people live without the divine inspiration that gives him, and people like him, access to higher insights about reality.

Socrates's idea that reality is unavailable to those who use their senses is what puts him at odds with the common man, and with common sense. Socrates says that he who sees with his eyes is blind, and this idea is most famously captured in his allegory of the cave, and more explicitly in his description of the divided line. The allegory of the cave (begins Republic 7.514a) is a paradoxical analogy wherein Socrates argues that the invisible world is the most intelligible ("noeton") and that the visible world ("(h)oraton") is the least knowable, and the most obscure. (This is exactly the opposite of what Socrates says to Euthyphro in the soothsayer's namesake dialogue. There, Socrates tells Euthyphro that people can agree on matters of logic and science, and are divided on moral matters, which are not so easily verifiable.)

Socrates says in the Republic that people who take the sun-lit world of the senses to be good and real are living pitifully in a den of evil and ignorance. Socrates admits that few climb out of the den, or cave of ignorance, and those who do, not only have a terrible struggle to attain the heights, but when they go back down for a visit or to help other people up, they find themselves objects of scorn and ridicule.

According to Socrates, physical objects and physical events are "shadows" of their ideal or perfect forms, and exist only to the extent that they instantiate the perfect versions of themselves. Just as shadows are temporary, inconsequential epiphenomena produced by physical objects, physical objects are themselves fleeting phenomena caused by more substantial causes, the ideals of which they are mere instances. For example, Socrates thinks that perfect justice exists (although it is not clear where) and his own trial would be a cheap copy of it.

The allegory of the cave (often said by scholars to represent Plato's own epistemology and metaphysics) is intimately connected to his political ideology (often said to also be Plato's own), that only people who have climbed out of the cave and cast their eyes on a vision of goodness are fit to rule. Socrates claims that the enlightened men of society must be forced from their divine contemplations and compelled to run the city according to their lofty insights. Thus is born the idea of the "philosopher-king", the wise person who accepts the power thrust upon him by the people who are wise enough to choose a good master. This is the main thesis of Socrates in the Republic, that the most wisdom the masses can muster is the wise choice of a ruler.

The word metaphysics derives from the fact that Aristotle's musings about divine reality came after ("meta") his lecture notes on his treatise on nature ("physics"). The term is in fact applied to Aristotle's own teacher, and Plato's "metaphysics" is understood as Socrates' division of reality into the warring and irreconcilable domains of the material and the spiritual. The theory has been of incalculable influence in the history of Western philosophy and religion.

Main article: Theory of Forms
The Theory of Forms typically refers to Plato's belief that the material world as it seems to us is not the real world, but only a shadow of the real world. Plato spoke of forms in formulating his solution to the problem of universals. The forms, according to Plato, are roughly speaking archetypes or abstract representations of the many types and properties (that is, of universals) of things we see all around us.

Main article: Platonic epistemology
Many have interpreted Plato as stating that knowledge is justified true belief, an influential view which informed future developments in modern analytic epistemology. This interpretation is based on a reading of the Theaetetus wherein Plato argues that belief is to be distinguished from knowledge on account of justification. Many years later, Edmund Gettier famously demonstrated the problems of the justified true belief account of knowledge. This interpretation, however, imports modern analytic and empiricist categories onto Plato himself and is better read on its own terms than as Plato's view.

Really, in the Sophist, Statesman, Republic, and the Parmenides Plato himself associates knowledge with the apprehension of unchanging Forms and their relationships to one another (which he calls "expertise" in Dialectic). More explicitly, Plato himself argues in the Timaeus that knowledge is always proportionate to the realm from which it is gained. In other words, if one derives their account of something experientially, because the world of sense is in flux, the views therein attained will be mere opinions. And opinions are characterized by a lack of necessity and stability. On the other hand, if one derives their account of something by way of the non-sensible forms, because these forms are unchanging, so too is the account derived from them. It is only in this sense that Plato uses the term "knowledge."

In the Meno, Socrates uses a geometrical example to expound Plato's view that knowledge in this latter sense is acquired by recollection. Socrates elicits a fact concerning a geometrical construction from a slave boy, who could not have otherwise known the fact (due to the slave boy's lack of education). The knowledge must be present, Socrates concludes, in an eternal, non-experiential form.

Papirus Oxyrhynchus, with fragment of Plato's RepublicPlato's philosophical views had many societal implications, especially on the idea of an ideal state or government. There is some discrepancy between his early and later views. Some of the most famous doctrines are contained in the Republic during his middle period, as well as in the Laws and the Statesman. However, because Plato wrote dialogues, it is assumed that Socrates is often speaking for Plato. This assumption may not be true in all cases.

Plato, through the words of Socrates, asserts that societies have a tripartite class structure corresponding to the appetite/spirit/reason structure of the individual soul. The appetite/spirit/reason stand for different parts of the body. The body parts symbolize the castes of society.

Productive Which represents the abdomen.(Workers) — the labourers, carpenters, plumbers, masons, merchants, farmers, ranchers, etc. These correspond to the "appetite" part of the soul.
Protective Which represents the chest.(Warriors or Guardians) — those who are adventurous, strong and brave; in the armed forces. These correspond to the "spirit" part of the soul.
Governing Which represents the head. (Rulers or Philosopher Kings) — those who are intelligent, rational, self-controlled, in love with wisdom, well suited to make decisions for the community. These correspond to the "reason" part of the soul and are very few.
According to this model, the principles of Athenian democracy (as it existed in his day) are rejected as only a few are fit to rule. Instead of rhetoric and persuasion, Plato says reason and wisdom should govern. As Plato puts it:

"Until philosophers rule as kings or those who are now called kings and leading men genuinely and adequately philosophise, that is, until political power and philosophy entirely coincide, while the many natures who at present pursue either one exclusively are forcibly prevented from doing so, cities will have no rest from evils,... nor, I think, will the human race." (Republic 473c-d)

Plato in his academy, drawing after a painting by Swedish painter Carl Johan WahlbomPlato describes these "philosopher kings" as "those who love the sight of truth" (Republic 475c) and supports the idea with the analogy of a captain and his ship or a doctor and his medicine. Sailing and health are not things that everyone is qualified to practice by nature. A large part of the Republic then addresses how the educational system should be set up to produce these philosopher kings.

However, it must be taken into account that the ideal city outlined in the Republic is qualified by Socrates as the ideal luxurious city, examined to determine how it is that injustice and justice grow in a city (Republic 372e). According to Socrates, the "true" and "healthy" city is instead the one first outlined in book II of the Republic, 369c–372d, containing farmers, craftsmen, merchants, and wage-earners, but lacking the guardian class of philosopher-kings as well as delicacies such as "perfumed oils, incense, prostitutes, and pastries", in addition to paintings, gold, ivory, couches, a multitude of occupations such as poets and hunters, and war.

In addition, the ideal city is used as an image to illuminate the state of one's soul, or the will, reason, and desires combined in the human body. Socrates is attempting to make an image of a rightly ordered human, and then later goes on to describe the different kinds of humans that can be observed, from tyrants to lovers of money in various kinds of cities. The ideal city is not promoted, but only used to magnify the different kinds of individual humans and the state of their soul. However, the philosopher king image was used by many after Plato to justify their personal political beliefs. The philosophic soul according to Socrates has reason, will, and desires united in virtuous harmony. A philosopher has the moderate love for wisdom and the courage to act according to wisdom. Wisdom is knowledge about the Good or the right relations between all that exists.

Wherein it concerns states and rulers, Plato has made interesting arguments. For instance he asks which is better - a bad democracy or a country reigned by a tyrant. He argues that it is better to be ruled by a bad tyrant, than be a bad democracy (since here all the people are now responsible for such actions, rather than one individual committing many bad deeds.) This is emphasised within the Republic as Plato describes the event of mutiny onboard a ship.Plato suggests the ships crew to be in line with the democratic rule of many and the captain, although inhibited through ailments, the tyrant. Plato's description of this event is parallel to that of democracy within the state and the inherent problems that arise.

According to Plato, a state which is made up of different kinds of souls, will overall decline from an aristocracy (rule by the best) to a timocracy (rule by the honorable), then to an oligarchy (rule by the few), then to a democracy (rule by the people), and finally to tyranny (rule by one person, rule by a tyrant)[citation needed].

For a long time Plato's unwritten doctrine had been considered unworthy of attention. Most of the books on Plato seem to diminish its importance. Nevertheless the first important witness who mentions its existence is Aristotle, who in his Physics (209 b) writes: "It is true, indeed, that the account he gives there [i.e. in Timaeus] of the participant is different from what he says in his so-called unwritten teaching (ἄγραφα δόγματα)." The term ἄγραφα δόγματα literally means unwritten doctrine and it stands for the most fundamental metaphysical teaching of Plato which he disclosed only to his most trusted fellows and kept secret from the public.

The reason for not revealing it to everyone is partially discussed in Phaedrus (276 c) where Plato criticizes the written transmission of knowledge as faulty, favoring instead the spoken logos: "he who has knowledge of the just and the good and beautiful ... will not, when in earnest, write them in ink, sowing them through a pen with words which cannot defend themselves by argument and cannot teach the truth effectually." The same argument is repeated in Plato's Seventh Letter (344 c): "every serious man in dealing with really serious subjects carefully avoids writing." In the same letter he writes (341 c): "I can certainly declare concerning all these writers who claim to know the subjects which I seriously study ... there does not exist, nor will there ever exist, any treatise of mine dealing therewith." Such secrecy is necessary in order not "to expose them to unseemly and degrading treatment" (344 d).

It is however said that Plato once disclosed this knowledge to the public in his lecture On the Good (∏ερὶ τἀγαθοῦ), in which the Good (τὸ ἀγαθόν) is identified with the One (the Unity, τὸ ἕν), the fundamental ontological principle. The content of this lecture has been transmitted by several witnesses, among others Aristoxenus who describes the event in the following words: "Each came expecting to learn something about the things which are generally considered good for men, such as wealth, good health, physical strength, and altogether a kind of wonderful happiness. But when the mathematical demonstrations came, including numbers, geometrical figures and astronomy, and finally the statement Good is One seemed to them, I imagine, utterly unexpected and strange; hence some belittled the matter, while others rejected it." Simplicius quotes Alexander of Aphrodisias who states that "according to Plato, the first principles of everything, including the Forms themselves are One and Indefinite Duality (ἡ ἀόριστος δυάς) which he called Large and Small (τὸ μέγα καὶ τὸ μικρόν) ... one might also learn this from Speusippus and Xenocrates and the others who were present at Plato's lecture on the Good"

Their account is in full agreement with Aristotle's description of Plato's metaphysical doctrine. In Metaphysics he writes: "Now since the Forms are the causes of everything else, he [i.e. Plato] supposed that their elements are the elements of all things. Accordingly the material principle is the Great and Small [i.e. the Dyad], and the essence is the One (τὸ ἕν), since the numbers are derived from the Great and Small by participation in the One" (987 b). "From this account it is clear that he only employed two causes: that of the essence, and the material cause; for the Forms are the cause of the essence in everything else, and the One is the cause of it in the Forms. He also tells us what the material substrate is of which the Forms are predicated in the case of sensible things, and the One in that of the Forms - that it is this the duality (the Dyad, ἡ δυάς), the Great and Small (τὸ μέγα καὶ τὸ μικρόν). Further, he assigned to these two elements respectively the causation of good and of evil" (988 a).

The most important aspect of this interpretation of Plato's metaphysics is the continuity between his teaching and the neoplatonic interpretation of Plotinus or Ficino which has been considered erroneous by many but may in fact have been directly influenced by oral transmission of Plato's doctrine. The first scholar who recognized the importance of the unwritten doctrine of Plato was Heinrich Gomperz who described it in his speech during the 7th International Congress of Philosophy in 1930. All the sources related to the ἄγραφα δόγματα have been collected by Konrad Gaiser and published as Testimonia Platonica.

http://zhidao.baidu.com/question/7396855.html?si=1
这是莎士比亚的。应该符合你的要求了

去wikipedia英文网站搜下 就可以了

  • 娆叉眰鑻忔牸鎷夊簳\浜氶噷澹寰穃鏌忔媺鍥鐨勪釜浜鑻辨枃浠嬬粛
    绛旓細Adeimantus and Glaucon, and a daughter Potone, the mother of Speusippus (the nephew and successor of Plato as head of his philosophical Academy).[5] According to the Republic, Adeimantus and Glaucon were older than Plato.[6] Nevertheless, in his Memorabilia, Xenophon presents...
  • 鏌忔媺鍥涓讳箟鏄粈涔堜富涔?浠栨槸瀹楁暀淇′话鑰呭悧?
    绛旓細渚濇嵁鍚庢潵绗鏍瑰凹路鎷夊皵淇殑璇存硶锛屾煆鎷夊浘鐨勫師鍚嶄负浜氶噷鏂鍏嬪嫆鏂紙Aristokles锛夛紝鍚庢潵鍥犱负浠栧己澹殑韬函鑰岃绉颁负鏌忔媺鍥撅紙鍦ㄥ笇鑵婅涓紝Platus涓璇嶆槸鈥滃钩鍧︺佸闃斺濈瓑鎰忔濓級銆備絾绗鏍瑰凹涔熸彁璧蜂簡鍏朵粬鐨勮娉曪紝鏌忔媺鍥捐繖涓悕瀛愪篃鍙兘鏄潵鑷粬娴佺晠瀹藉箍锛坧latut锚s锛夌殑鍙f墠銆佹垨鍥犱负浠栨嫢鏈夊骞跨殑鍓嶉銆傜敱浜庢煆鎷夊浘鍑鸿壊鐨勫涔...
  • 鏌忔媺鍥鏄粈涔?
    绛旓細渚濇嵁鍚庢潵绗鏍瑰凹路鎷夊皵淇殑璇存硶,鏌忔媺鍥剧殑鍘熷悕涓轰簹閲屾柉澶氬厠鍕掓柉(Aristokles),鍚庢潵鍥犱负浠栧己澹殑韬函鑰岃绉颁负鏌忔媺鍥(鍦ㄥ笇鑵婅涓,Platus涓璇嶆槸鈥滃钩鍧︺佸闃斺濈瓑鎰忔)銆備絾绗鏍瑰凹涔熸彁璧蜂簡鍏朵粬鐨勮娉,鏌忔媺鍥捐繖涓悕瀛愪篃鍙兘鏄潵鑷粬娴佺晠瀹藉箍(platut锚s)鐨勫彛鎵嶃佹垨鍥犱负浠栨嫢鏈夊骞跨殑鍓嶉銆傜敱浜庢煆鎷夊浘鍑鸿壊鐨勫涔犺兘鍔涘拰鍏朵粬鎵嶅崕,鍙...
  • 鈥 鏌忔媺鍥鈥濇槸浠涔堟剰鎬?
    绛旓細鏌忔媺鍥(鑻辫瘧锛歅lato 甯岃厞璇細鈭徫ά蟿蠅谓)鐢熷崚锛氬ぇ绾﹀叕鍏冨墠427骞达紞鍓347骞达級璐$尞锛氫笉浠呮槸鍙ゅ笇鑵婂摬瀛︼紝涔熸槸鍏ㄩ儴瑗挎柟鍝插涔冭嚦鏁翠釜瑗挎柟鏂囧寲鏈浼熷ぇ鐨勫摬瀛﹀鍜屾濇兂瀹朵箣涓銆傛煆鎷夊浘寮忔亱鐖憋紝涔熺О涓烘煆鎷夊浘寮忕埍鎯咃紝浠ヨタ鏂瑰摬瀛﹀鏌忔媺鍥惧懡鍚嶇殑涓绉嶅紓鎬ч棿鐨勭簿绁炴亱鐖憋紝杩芥眰蹇冪伒娌熼氾紝鎺掓枼鑲夋銆傛渶鏃╃敱Marsilio Ficino...
  • 鏌忔媺鍥剧畝浠 鍙ゅ笇鑵婂摬瀛﹀鏌忔媺鍥句笌浠栫殑鎬濇兂
    绛旓細涓嶈繃涓や汉涔嬮棿鐨勫叧绯讳篃浠嶆湁浜夎銆備緷鎹悗鏉ョ娆ф牴灏悸锋媺灏斾慨鐨勮娉曪紝鏌忔媺鍥剧殑鍘熷悕涓轰簹閲屾柉澶氬厠鍕掓柉 (Aristokles) 锛屽悗鏉ュ洜涓轰粬寮哄.鐨勮韩韬岃绉颁负鏌忔媺鍥 (鍦ㄥ笇鑵婅涓紝Platus涓璇嶆槸銆屽钩鍧︺佸闃斻嶇瓑鎰忔) 銆備絾绗鏍瑰凹涔熸彁璧蜂簡鍏朵粬鐨勮娉曪紝鏌忔媺鍥捐繖涓悕瀛椾篃鍙兘鏄潵鑷粬娴佺晠瀹藉箍 (platutes) 鐨勫彛鎵嶃...
  • 鏌忔媺鍥:璇椾汉浜氶噷澹寰
    绛旓細浜氶噷澹寰(鍏厓鍓 384-322 骞)鏄鏌忔媺鍥鏈钁楀悕鐨勫鐢,鍑犱箮娌℃湁鎻愪緵鍏充簬浠栫殑浼犺淇℃伅,鑰屼笖澶ч儴鍒嗗垢瀛樹笅鏉ョ殑鏌忔媺鍥剧殑淇′欢閮借璁や负鏄悗鏉ヤ负浜嗚瘉瀹炰粬浣滀负鍝插瀹剁殑澹拌獕鑰屽啓鐨勮禎鍝併侱iogenes Laertius 瀵规煆鎷夊浘鐨勭敓骞虫彁渚涗簡鏈鍏ㄩ潰鐨勬弿杩,鍦ㄤ粬姝诲悗鐨勫嚑涓笘绾噷鍐欎笅浜嗕粬鐨勮憲浣,浣嗕粠鏈紩鐢ㄨ繃浠栫殑璧勬枡鏉ユ簮銆 浜氶噷澹寰锋垚涓...
  • 鈥鏌忔媺鍥鐨勬案鎭掆濊瘧鎴鑻辨枃
    绛旓細adj.1. 鏌忔媺鍥(Plato)鐨勶紝 鏌忔媺鍥惧摬瀛︾殑 2. [p-]绾弸璋婄殑锛涚函绮剧鎭嬬埍鐨 eternity [ɪˈtɜːnɪtɪ]n. -ties 1. 鏃犵┓鏃犲敖锛涙案鎭 2. 寰堥暱鏃堕棿 Longman Dictionary of Contemporary English Plato Pla路to (?427-347BC) an ancient Greek ...
  • 鏌忔媺鍥浠涔堟剰鎬
    绛旓細鐞嗘兂鍥解濇柟妗堬紝涓诲紶鈥滃摬瀛︾帇鈥濇潵娌荤悊鍥藉锛屾妸鈥滃摬瀛︾帇鈥濈湅浣滃ぉ涓荤殑缁熸不鑰呫佺珛娉曡咃紝浠栫殑鏀挎不鎬濇兂甯︽湁绌烘兂鐨勬ц川銆傝憲鏈夈婄悊鎯冲浗銆嬨併婃硶寰嬬瘒銆嬨併婂反闂ㄥ凹寰风瘒銆嬨併婁細楗瘒銆嬨併婃櫤鑰呯瘒銆嬨併婃枑澶氱瘒銆嬨併婃嘲闃挎嘲寰风瘒銆嬨併婅拏杩堟绡囥嬬瓑銆傞櫎姝や箣澶栵紝鏌忔媺鍥鐨勭埍鎯呮寚鐨勬槸绮剧鎭嬬埍锛屾棤鎬х敓娲荤殑鐖辨儏 ...
  • 鐢ㄨ嫳鏂囦粙缁涓浗鐨勫啗浜,100瀛椾互涓
    绛旓細With 2.3 million active troops, the People's Liberation Army (PLA) is the largest standing military force in the world, commanded by the Central Military Commission (CMC).[182] The PLA consists of the People's Liberation Army Ground Force (PLAGF), the People's Liberation Army ...
  • Le vent se l猫ve, il faut tenter de vivre鏄粈涔堟剰鎬,鍑鸿嚜鍝猒鐧惧害...
    绛旓細骞朵笉鏄负浣犱滑鐭虫澘涓嬮暱鐪犵殑澶т紬, 瀹冨氨闈犵敓鍛借岀敓娲,瀹冧粠涓嶇寮鎴! 鐖辨儏鍚?涔熻鏄鎴戣嚜宸辩殑鎲庢仺? 瀹冧竴鍓瀵嗙殑鐗欓娇鎬昏窡鎴戞帴杩, 鐢ㄤ粈涔堝悕瀛楁潵鍙畠閮戒細閫傚疁! 绠″畠鍛!瀹冭兘鐬,鑳借,瀹冭兘鎯,鑳界, 瀹冨枩娆㈡垜鐨勮倝,瀹冧細杩介殢鎴戜笂搴, 鎴戞椿鐫灏卞洜涓轰粠灞炰簬瀹冭繖鐐圭敓鏈! 榻愯!娈嬪繊鐨勯綈璇!浼婇噷浜氶綈璇! 浣犵敤涓鏋氱绌块...
  • 扩展阅读:免费翻译器拍照 ... 扫一扫识别英文 ... 英文翻译中文在线翻译 ... 扫一扫识别图片来源 ... 中英文自动翻译器 ... 翻译器中英文转换 ... 免费的翻译器 ... [pl.]英文里代表什么 ... 中英文转换键ctrl+ ...

    本站交流只代表网友个人观点,与本站立场无关
    欢迎反馈与建议,请联系电邮
    2024© 车视网